Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is perhaps the single most influential figure in the pre-twentieth-century history of cognitive research. He was a devoutly religious man from a very humble background: his father was a saddlemaker. Though one-quarter Scottish (it is said that Kant is a Germanization of Candt), he lived his whole life in Königsberg (now Kaliningrad), just below Lithuania. By his death he was virtually the official philosopher of the German-speaking world.
Until middle age, he was a prominent rationalist in the tradition of Leibniz and Wolff. Then DAVID HUME, as he put it, "awoke me from my dogmatic slumbers." The critical philosophy ensued. One of its fundamental questions was, what must we be like to have the experiences we have? The view of the mind that Kant developed to answer this question framed virtually all cognitive research until very re-cently.
Philosophy of mind and knowledge were by no means the only areas in which Kant made seminal contributions. He founded physical geometry. (Fieldwork must not have been too important -- he is said never to have traveled more than thirty-five miles from Königsberg in his whole life!) His work on political philosophy grounds modern liberal democratic theory. And his deontology put ethics on a new footing, one that remains influential to this day.
It is his view of the mind, however, that influenced cognitive research. Four things in particular shaped subsequent thought:
Indeed, Kant's notorious "noumenalism" about the mind might be simply an early expression of FUNCTIONALISM. Noumenalism is the idea that we cannot know what the mind is like, not even something as basic as whether it is simple or complex. Part of Kant's argument is that we cannot infer how the mind is built from how it functions: function does not determine form. (The other part is an equally contemporary-sounding rejection of INTROSPECTION. Both arguments occur in his most important treatment of the mind, the chapter attacking rationalism's paralogisms of pure reason in the Critique of Pure Reason.)
Kant also developed important ideas about the mind that have not played much of a role in subsequent cognitive research, though perhaps they should have. Two of them concern mental unity.
Finally, Kant articulated some striking ideas about:
In sum, Kant articulated the view of the mind behind most of cognitive science (see Brook 1994 for further discussion).
Brook, A. (1994). Kant and the Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Castañeda, H.-N. (1966). "He": A study in the logic of self consciousness. Ratio 8:130-157.
Fodor, J. (1983). Modularity of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Kant, I. (1781/1787). Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan, 1963.
Sellars, W. (1968). Science and Metaphysics. New York: Humanities Press.
Shoemaker, S. (1968). Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy 65(2):555-567.
Treisman, A., and G. Gelade. (1980). A feature-integration theory of attention. Cognitive Psychology 12:97-136.
Ameriks, K. (1983). Kant's Theory of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brook, A. (1994). Kant and the Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Falkenstein, L. (1996). Kant's Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Kant, I. (1798). Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. Trans. Mary Gregor. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974.
Kitcher, P. (1990). Kant's Transcendental Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press .