Semantics is the study of MEANING. It is not surprising that "semantics" can "mean" different things to different researchers within cognitive science. Notions relating to meaning have had long (and often contentious) histories within the disciplines that contribute to cognitive science, and there have been very diverse views concerning what questions are important, and for what purposes, and how they should be approached. And there are some deep foundational and methodological differences within and across disciplines that affect approaches to semantics. These have partly impeded but also stimulated cooperative discussion and fruitful cross-fertilization of ideas, and there has been great substantive progress in semantics, in the sister field of PRAGMATICS and at the SYNTAX-SEMANTICS INTERFACE in recent decades.
The logico-philosophical tradition divides semiotics (the study of signs, applicable to both natural and constructed languages) into syntax, semantics, and pragmatics (Morris 1938). On this view, SYNTAX concerns properties of expressions, such as well-formedness; semantics concerns relations between expressions and what they are "about" (typically "the world" or some model), such as reference; and pragmatics concerns relations between expressions and their uses in context, such as IMPLICATURE. Some approaches reject the characterization of semantics as dealing with relations between language and something external to language, especially between language and "the world" (see (1) and (2) below). And many approaches have challenged, in different ways, the autonomy of semantics from pragmatics implied by the traditional trichotomy. We return to some of these foundational issues below.
One of the basic issues that any theory of semantics must deal with is how we can understand the meanings of novel sentences. Syntax describes the recursive part-whole structure of sentences; semantics must account for how the meanings of smaller parts are combined to form the meanings of larger wholes (see COMPOSITIONALITY and LOGICAL FORM). There are many controversial issues surrounding the principle of compositionality, which contains several crucially theory-dependent terms: The meaning of an expression is a function of the meanings of its parts and of how they are syntactically combined. But most explicit semantic theories, especially formal semantics, accept it as a basic working principle. The extension of compositional semantics beyond the level of the sentence, to the interpretation of DISCOURSE, has been of increasing importance.
Another basic issue for semantic theory is the nature of the meanings of the smallest meaningful units of language, words or morphemes (or even smaller units if some morphemes are viewed as decomposable into submorphemic "features"). Lexical semantics has an even longer history than compositional semantics and is connected with the most fundamental problems in the philosophy of language and the psychology of CONCEPTS (see REFERENCE, THEORIES OF and LEXICON).
Crucial interfaces include the syntax-semantics interface and the interfaces of semantics with pragmatics, with encyclopedic and common-sense knowledge, and perhaps directly with PHONOLOGY (e.g., with respect to the semantic/pragmatic interpretation of PROSODY AND INTONATION). Other important areas of research concern acquisition, human semantic processing, and computational semantics.
Among the most important semantic properties of linguistic expressions that need to be accounted for, most semanticists would include the following:
Ambiguity: Having more than one meaning. Strongly compositional theories require all semantic ambiguity to reflect either lexical or structural (syntactic) AMBIGUITY.
Vagueness: A challenge for some theories of the nature of word meanings as well as to classical theories of concepts. Drawing the distinction between ambiguity and VAGUENESS is a classic problem (Quine 1960; Zwicky and Sadock 1975).
Anomaly: Some expressions, like the famous Colorless green ideas sleep furiously (Chomsky 1957), are judged to be semantically anomalous although syntactically well-formed. The lines between semantic and other sorts of anomaly are crucially theory-dependent and often debated.
Entailment: Sentence A entails sentence B if sentence B is true in every possible state of affairs in which sentence A is true. Entailment has always been a central semantic concern in LOGIC and the philosophy of language, and remains so in POSSIBLE WORLDS SEMANTICS. Cognitive semanticists replace concern with logical entailment by concern with human inference; formal semanticists see the relation of entailment to actual human inference as indirect. But most semanticists are concerned with some notion of entailment or inference, and many agree about the importance of revising (incrementally or radically) the formal logics invented by logicians to model the "natural logic(s)" implicit in the semantics of natural languages.
Presupposition: A precondition for the felicity or truth- valuedness of an expression in a context. PRESUPPOSITION research has been important in theorizing about the relation between (or possible integration of) semantics and pragmatics.
Context: Expressions are interpreted in the (linguistic) context of other expressions, and in the (nonlinguistic) context of an utterance situation in which the participants have various beliefs and intentions. Any approach to semantics has to take a stand on the relation of "semantics proper" to various aspects of context, including the treatment of INDEXICALS AND DEMONSTRATIVES (Kaplan 1977). One important trend in formal semantics has been the shift from "meanings as truth conditions" to "meanings as functions from contexts to contexts" (with truth conditions as a corollary; Heim 1982); see CONTEXT AND POINT OF VIEW, SITUATEDNESS/EMBEDDEDNESS, DYNAMIC SEMANTICS.
Referential opacity: The construction exemplified in "Jones is seeking --" is referentially opaque, because the substitution of one coreferential expression for another in that context does not always preserve the truth-value of the whole. It may be true that Jones is seeking the president and false that Jones is seeking Mary's father even though the president is Mary's father. Frege's distinction between SENSE AND REFERENCE, Carnap's distinction between intension and extension, and Montague's intensional logic all treat the phenomenon of referential opacity, pervasive in PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE constructions.
Other issues important to semantics include ANAPHORA, negation and QUANTIFIERS, TENSE AND ASPECT, and modality; other issues important for semantics and pragmatics together include topic- FOCUS structure and the interpretation of questions, imperatives, and other speech acts.
Many foundational issues of semantics are relevant to cognitive science; some are particularly linguistic, others overlap heavily with issues in the philosophy of language and philosophy of mind. We mention a few central issues that divide different approaches to semantics.
Apresjan, J. D. (1974). Leksicheskaja Semantika (Lexical semantics, 1992). Moscow: Nauka and Ann Arbor, MI: Karoma.
Austin, J. L. (1962). How to Do Things with Words. London: Oxford University Press.
Bach, E. (1986). Natural language metaphysics. In R. B. Marcus, G. J. W. Dorn, and P. Weingartner, Eds., Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science 7. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 573-595.
Carnap, R. (1956). Meaning and Necessity. 2nd ed. with supplements. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. New York: Praeger.
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.
Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung (On sense and reference). Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100:25-50. Reprinted in P. T. Geach and M. Black, Eds., Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (1952). Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 56 - 78.
Heim, I. (1982). The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite NPs. Ph.D. diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Jackendoff, R. (1983). Semantics and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, R. (1995). Semantic Structures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, R. (1996). Semantics and cognition. In S. Lappin, Ed., The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 539-559.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental Models: Towards a Cognitive Science of Language, Inference, and Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kaplan, D. (1977). The logic of demonstratives. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8:81-98.
Kretzmann, N. (1967). Semantics, history of. In P. Edwards, Ed. in chief, The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 7. New York: Macmillan, pp. 358-406.
Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lewis, D. (1975). Languages and language. In K. Gunderson, Ed., Language, Mind, and Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3-35.
Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, and P. Suppes, Eds., Approaches to Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 221-242. Reprinted in R. Montague, (1974). Formal Philosophy: Selected Papers of Richard Montague, R. Thomason, Ed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, pp. 247 - 270.
Morris, C. W. (1938). Foundation of the theory of signs. In O. Neurath, R. Carnap, and C. Morris, Eds., International Encyclopaedia of Unified Science 1, no. 2. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 1-59.
Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. In K. Gunderson, Ed., Language, Mind, and Knowledge. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 131-193. Reprinted in H. Putnam, (1975). Mind, language, and reality. Mind, language, and reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 215 - 271.
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wierzbicka, A. (1985). Lexicography and Conceptual Analysis. Ann Arbor, MI: Karoma.
Zwicky, A., and J. M. Sadock. (1975). Ambiguity tests and how to fail them. In J. P. Kimball, Ed., Syntax and Semantics 4. New York: Academic Press, pp.1-36.
Bach, E. (1989). Informal Lectures on Formal Semantics. Albany: SUNY Press.
Chierchia, G., and S. McConnell-Ginet. (1990). Meaning and Grammar: An Introduction to Semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cresswell, M. J. (1978). Semantic competence. In M. Guenthner-Reutter and F. Guenthner, Eds., Meaning and Translation: Philosophical and Linguistic Approaches. London: Duckworth.
Davidson, D. (1970). Semantics for natural languages. In B. Visentini et al., Eds., Linguaggi nella Società e nella Tecnica. Milan: Edizioni di Comunità.
Dowty, D. (1979). Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Dowty, D., R. Wall, and S. Peters. (1981). Introduction to Montague Semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Fillmore, C. J. (1982). Frame semantics. In The Linguistic Society of Korea, Ed., Linguistics in the Morning Calm. Seoul: Hanshin Pub. Co., pp. 111-137.
Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gamut, L. T. F. (1991). Logic, Language, and Meaning. Vol. 2: Intensional Logic and Logical Grammar. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Heim, I., and A. Kratzer. (1997). Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.
Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, and M. Stokhof, Eds., Formal Methods in the Study of Language: Proceedings of the Third Amsterdam Colloquium. Amsterdam: Mathematical Centre Tracts, pp. 277-322. Reprinted in J. Groenendijk, T. M. V. Janssen, and M. Stokhof, Eds. Truth, Interpretation, and Information (1984). GRASS 2. Dordrecht: Foris.
Katz, J. J. (1981). Language and Other Abstract Objects. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.
Lappin, S., Ed. (1996). The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Larson, R., and G. Segal. (1995). Knowledge of Meaning: An Introduction to Semantic Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese 22:18-67. Reprinted in D. Davidson and G. Harman, Eds., Semantics of Natural Language (1972). Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 169 - 218.
Lyons, J. (1988). Principles of Linguistic Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Partee, B. (1979). Semantics: Mathematics or psychology? In R. Bauerle, U. Egli, and A. von Stechow, Eds., Semantics from Different Points of View. Berlin: Springer, pp. 1-14.
Partee, B. (1995). Lexical semantics and compositionality. In D. Osherson, Gen. Ed., L. Gleitman, and M. Liberman, Eds., Invitation to Cognitive Science. Vol. 1, Language. 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 311-360.
Partee, B. (1996). The development of formal semantics in linguistic theory. In S. Lappin, Ed., The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 11-38.
Sgall, P., E. Hajiová, and J. Panevová. (1986). The Meaning of the Sentence in Its Semantic and Pragmatic Aspects. Prague: Academia; and Dordrecht: Reidel.
Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole, Ed., Syntax and Semantics. Vol. 9, Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press, pp. 315-332.
Stechow, A. von, and D. Wunderlich, Eds. (1991). Semantik/ Semantics: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research. Berlin: Mouton.
Talmy, L. (1991). Path to realization: A typology of event conflation. In Buffalo Papers in Linguistics. State University of New York at Buffalo, pp. 147-187.
Van Benthem, J., and A. ter Meulen, Eds. (1997). Handbook of Logic and Language. Amsterdam: Elsevier.